Total Pageviews
Sunday, December 18, 2011
Iphone 5, Facebook, Google+: A New World
What can Facebook, iphone 5 and Google+ tell us about our motivations and our economy? You spend hours on Facebook, eagerly search for friends on Google+, and you would sell all duplicate organs to any black-market organ dealer with a dirty butter knife to get the iphone 5.
These things have one thing in common, one primary motivator. They're all social. This is remarkable for one reason. Generally, we motivate people with secondary reinforcers which are not social. We use grades, money and threat to keep people doing what we think they ought to do. Hell, we think we need them to keep us doing what we think we should do and even what we want to do.
Wikipedia Link About Google Plus |
We're trapped by tertiary tokens. They're tertiary in that they don't have an intrinsic link to what we do for them, and their tokens because they're meaningless outside our agreement (except threats). For instance, a grade is given as a signifier or achievement, of getting beyond a class, but it doesn't contain any direct motivation to learn. In fact, you could get great grades without learning anything meaningful at all.
Money is the same. We think we need to pay people to achieve greatness. But, psychology shows over and over that great financial incentives might actually hinder productivity and creativity. So why, considering all the problems with tertiary tokens, and all the considerable amounts of time we spend on Facebook, Google+, all the money (or organs) we hope to spend on the new iphone 5 do we think we that money and grades are the best reinforcers and motivators---why when it's obvious that the greatest reinforcers are social in nature.
Why haven't we moved to an economy that takes advantage of development for the sake of mastery in social context, and why haven't we moved from educational systems that work on grades to systems that facilities the intrinsically social nature of knowledge to have learning in motion? It seems like laziness. No, it is laziness--and it is fear.
We say, "It's the best we have!" but we've deluded ourselves. It's not the best we have; it's the best we had. We just don't have the character and strength to apply the knowledge that we've gained over the last 100 years to our world. It might inconvenience us. By us I mean: Those who have the comfort of a developed system. We made it the old system and we don't want to learn another even if it is better for the world. We feel safe there.
So while the world and the market goes on revealing the nature of a healthier more productive world with sites like Facebook and Google+, and products like the iphone 5, we continue in our old ways, sacrificing a better way because we made it in an old world.
Labels:
College,
conditioning,
Education,
freedom of choice,
google plus facebook,
google+,
iphone 5,
motivation,
occupy wall street,
operant conditioning,
philosophy,
RSA animate,
socialism,
Steve Jobs,
university
Tuesday, December 13, 2011
The Philosophy of Chatroulette and Freedom: The Impossibility of Free Will
Have you ever been really bored--I mean REALLY bored--and jumped on Chatroulette (link to Wiki)? You know the nights I'm talking about: Facebook Chat is empty, your significant other is asleep and you've gone and drank 6 cups of coffee, thoughtlessly---And, done so just an hour before your obviously optional bedtime? Think about who you chose to spend time chatting with on Chatroulette (link to Chatroulette.com). Did you actually choose them? Did you sit and think: "this is what I want, this is the specific trait I'm looking for in a conversation, and I'll apply all this in the split second before I or the other person hits 'NEXT'"? I know I don't.
You click "Start", some oddness draws you in, you realize what it is you're looking at---and quickly click "Next". Despite your permanent trauma, you're onto another oddity, and then another and another. Finally, you settle on a lonely girl from China, or some Wiccan trying to charge his badly drawn sigils. You didn't think about this; It just happend. So consider this moment of ambiguity in your the moment of decision. Did you chose this?
In some sense, you could say you chose this little moment of Chatroulette-voyeurism/conversation because it was you who acted. But, where was your Free Will? Did you choose the reasons out of which you chose that specific person? Did you choose your voyeuristic tendencies, your addiction to coffee or your manic need for company? I didn't. I don't. So what's what my point?
In other situations, any other situation, there is always this constitutive/necessary element of your choice---that thing that determines what you choose and chose---that you did not choose. Just like on Chatroulette, you cannot choose the reason out of which you choose. It's just more obvious on Chatroulette. Free will implies a choice of what causes you to choose. It implies that you are conscious of and constantly in control of everything that determines how you choose. This is impossible.
]This is the Chatroulette paradox: you cannot choose the reasons out of which you choose or it would lead to infinite regress. Either your choice is completely random (which also implies reasons (for another conversation)), or you have something driving the choice. There's always something driving the choice. You need to bottom out in some reason for acting. And, if a reason for acting is the necessary condition for you having chosen anything at all, then you couldn't have chosen those reasons.
Chatroulette provides an intuitive "bottoming out". (This is a double entendre (get it, Rock bottom?)). It provides a bottoming out because you didn't choose the reasons you acted: you simply acted. So next time you're on Chatroulette, consider the choices you make. You can't have free will, but realizing that might make you get introspective.
Resources on Choice and Free Will:
wikipedia.org Free Will
Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy Free Will
Wikipedia.org Choice
Resources on Choice and Free Will:
wikipedia.org Free Will
Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy Free Will
Wikipedia.org Choice
Labels:
Chatroulette,
Chatroulette trauma,
choice,
compulsion,
conversation,
Descartes,
dispositions,
Free Will,
freedom of choice,
Freewill,
mania,
Omegle,
philosophy,
Philosophy of psychiatry,
socrates,
solipsism
Saturday, December 10, 2011
To Reject or To Ignore, That is the Question
How do you deal with a person who just doesn't like you? Let's call her Cindy, for example's sake. You've gone through all the nice options: You've smiled at Cindy, bought her coffee and even invited Cindy out with you and your cadre of compadres. Now, Cindy isn't just someone you want as a friend, she's someone you interact with everyday at work and school, and who you desperately need affirmation from (she reminds you of mom). You played the nice card, and nice didn't work. Now, the only option you have is not-nice. So what not-nice option are you gonna take?
You could reject her. You could walk away when she talks to you, make rude comments about her and let it be known, "I don't like her". Or, you could ignore her. You could make it a point to act like she doesn't exist. When you walk by her desk, you keep looking at the cooler; when you see her on the street, you pretend like you don't; and when you're in class, you sit far away. You act like she someone you don't know.
An article in the Journal of Personality and Social psychology, shows that many times there's a difference in the kind of focus created in each method, whether you reject or ignore Cindy. It is likely that if you reject her, she will develop a prevention-focus. In other words, she's going to prevent feeling rejected--like by avoiding you. You don't want this to happen (though you really should) so you're left with only one option: Ignore her.
But, ignoring her isn't just your last options; it works. According to the article in the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, if you ignore her, you create a much different focus. Instead of making her want to escape the pain of rejection, you are likely to create something called a promotion-focus. A promotion-focus is obvious, it will make her feel the need to socialize with you. She will focus on promoting your relationship.
Out of the all the options--nice, reject or ignore--if nice doesn't workout, then: Ignore. Just be careful, don't take the ignoring too far or it becomes rejection. So if she tries to be nice, give her a little nice back. Keep a little mystery though.
Friday, December 9, 2011
Uniting Care Ethics, Nietzsche and Foucault
Any union of Care ethics and Nietzsche hammers on the senses, leaving the ring of “contradiction”
resounding in the mind. However, this may be apparent rather than actual. If we
read Nietzsche as speaking in more metaphorical than literal sense, as some
have suggested, and Nietzsche himself may have suggested (Montanari, 201; Nietzsche,
Ansell-Pearson & Diethe, 2007), then we discover that this is not as
certain a contradiction as it feels, and indeed Nietzsche’s supreme affirmation
of life might be realized in Care. Together, Nietzsche and Care offer a
critique of justice-based ethics, and with the help of Foucault a possible
foundation for a more appropriate ethical theory.
There are several problems
that need to be resolved before using Nietzsche and Care to create a critique
of Justice ethics. Some may interpret Care wrongly which would initiate a
damning critique of care using a Nietzschian critique. Nietzsche would disdain
a revaluing, or a will to power, that defines itself opposed to something else
that is strong and active and revalues a passivity as strength. Also, unlike
care, Nietzsche seems to promote the individual more than any kind of
relationship. However, as we’ll see this isn’t as much of problem as it seems,
and together the two perspectives merge to reveal that justice based ethics are
floating around with out content, without the perspective or the
individual.
When Carol Gilligan introduced what she thought was a poverty in modern ethics, she
labeled the sides Justice and care, where justice was the current paradigm and
understanding of ethics and Care represented a feminine perspective that might
be able to revalue ethics. I will use the terms Care and Justice ethics
broadly—encompassing many different ethical disciplines, much as she does—but I
will define them in a way that is informed by other Care thinkers. Justice will
be defined as that which starts from a universal, independent, atomist,
separate conception of a self and forms general rules from that self, and then
applies those general rules to specific cases, and that values rational control
over emotion, where emotions can only get in the way of ethical action. Care on
the other hand, I will define as an ethic that focuses on the specific, highly
contextual elements of a person in relationship. Care mbraces emotion as
providing a partial basis for morality and moral understanding, where there is
an appreciation and focus on attention, context and narrative, as well as, a
focus on communication in moral deliberation, where specific trumps the general.
At first, it feels
apparent that Nietzsche would be apposed to a Care ethics because it promotes,
well: care. However, you can read Nietzsche two ways. You can read him literally,
where the strong should have recourse to whatever makes them great. Or, you can
read him more metaphorically as some think he should be read, and he himself
implies (Montanari, 2011; Nietzsche et al.), and a different picture emerges.
In this construal, or interpretive lens, Nietzsche is only saying we should be
letting man be free to be great in activity, without the burden of feeling self
hate (Nietzsche et al.). Nietzsche wants continually forming exemplars,
something that affirms life, life that is only actualized in activity
(Montanari, 2011). Care ethics might be a development of this activity. There
is more to say about Neitzsche that affirms Care ethics, but we must deal with
the fact that Nietzsche would see anything as vile that redefines itself
against the strong and revalues activity as weakness and inactivity as strength
and some might see care ethics as affirming weakness.
This seems like a problem for Care ethics, as
it seems to be attempting to revalue something that has been considered
inherently weak, and even less human, as something strong (Held 1990). However,
there are two ways, broadly construed that an ethic of Care can be conceived.
The first may fall impotent prey to this critique. This perspective on Care can
be conceived of as a response to masculine domination, and an effort to revalue
the world, making the weakness of promotional inactivity inherent in femininity
to be considered strong. In this view, proponents of care would be defining
themselves against masculinities activity. This aspect or version of Care would
say masculinity devalues a woman’s place and makes her creature who has less
ethical potential than man, as a gender, and so it must be changed so that it
does not have this bias (Jaggar, 1995). However, to argue that that Care is
simply saying that it’s an unjust practice, so we need to revalue it would be
would be in error. It is certain that some of the motivation that facilitated
the perspective of care was a concern that women’s concerns were devalued.
However, that being as it may, there is a second stronger concern that predominates
in care and this is the Care that I refer to in the rest of the paper.
This version or aspect of Care doesn’t define
itself in antithesis to male domination; but, instead, it seeks to develop a
positive theory that can possibly replace Justice ethics and account for its
many flaws. This theory perceives a serious poverty in ethics that results from
certain historical assumptions that define the rules of the game that justice ethicists
are playing. They attempt to replace, or at very least inform, a justice ethic
that has been male dominated (Held, 1990). The Care ethicist, here, attacks a
conception of ethics that predominantly men formed from overly narrow, a priori
assumptions (Held, 1990; Jaggar, 1995). There’s good reason to believe the
second perspective is true, or at least more frequently true, of care ethics.
Most of the literature—like writings of Walker, Jaggar and Held—focus on the
narrow historical assumptions and impoverished concepts that they believe are
empty of any real meaning. In the formerly mentioned care perspective, the
perspective results from concerns about how women are valued; in the later,
care is a positive theory that results from a privileged perspective.
Virginia Held
(1990) reveals that the feminist or care ethicists are focused on the issue of
reality. She believes there is something about justice ethics that doesn’t
account for our lived in the world experience, where we are creatures in
social-emotional context. In addition, She holds that woman have a special
moral access because of their cultural role as caregivers to children. This
role makes them sensitive to the emotional, interpersonal elements of ethics.
It makes them sensitive to the emotional and self-constituting element of
relationships in ethical decisions. Men may not be as sensitive to this,
according to Held. And possibly as a result of Justice ethic’s lack of
perspectival privilege.
Due to the male domination of ethics, they’ve
created this unrealistic decontextualized, neutral “person”. The Justice
ethicist attempt to make sense of man socially (ethically) by postulating an
unrealistic, misleading fiction of man born and raised outside of culture (Held,
1990). So they’ve conceived of a general “person” and out of that created
ethical principles to apply to very specific, complex and situations. The
theoretical man without context isn’t a person at all because an actual person
is formed behaviorally and ethically within a family, with father, a mother and
all the inculcations that culture offers through practices and relationships.
Nietzsche adds to
this, in full agreement that this general man of justice is a fiction, and an
foolish place to start an ethic. Whereas for Care, Justice ethics doesn’t
account for the feeling person in context and through time; Nietzsche shows
that Justice ethicist can never know the agent they postulate because a person
is only ever known historically, after the fact, even the individual only
recognizes himself historically by remembering his actions (Montanari, 2011;
Nietzsche et al.). Because we are only ever looking at our actions in
hindsight, and from that evaluating who we are in the moment, we can only catch
glimpses of who we are (Montanari, 2011; Nietzsche et al.). Additionally,
through genealogy, looking at humans through history, we can only ever see the
contingency in what we have perceived to be necessary (Murdchadha, 2005), so to
postulate a fixed ideal would be gross a mistake and terrible assumption.
Both Care and
Nietzsche give a provocative attack on justice ethics but they also do more:
they may offer a replacement. They reveal that the foundations of justice
ethics, namely rationality, doesn’t provide complete access while claiming to
do so, and indeed it starts drawing conclusions from an assumption riddled
foundation of what it means to be a human agent. They show the oddness of
making inferences from a stripped down, de-contextualized, de-relationshiped person
to persons who are each individually born and raised in the highly variable context
of deep emotional social connections. Nietzsche complete this because he revealed
that you can only know yourself in part because you only know yourself as an
agent by looking back on a past action. But, now Foucault provides a way to
unify both perspectives. He exposes that the agent can only be realized historically
within relationship.
Foucault sensitizes
us to the fact that we are constitutively social creatures. We don’t simply
grow up as individuals in society; instead, our very individual identity form
from within our social relations, and as Held (1990) points out the content of
own law is “comprehensible” only in reference to norms, values and concepts.
All of these are constitutively social. Foucault elucidates how we as agents
are self-defining but only with the precondition of already presents ideas, rule
and practices that we didn’t invent ourselves. The practices we find ourselves within
define what counts as truth, and these are indeed not just limitations for
truth but the preconditions for any truth at all, including any self knowledge,
as culture defines how you are able to value yourself by defining what counts
as value. Foucault shows how we are the Nietzschian ideal of the active agent, but the
precondition for those actions to be counted as anything are that they are
counted as something by others, that what you do makes sense only within a
social context.
Here we get the
active agent, but who can only do so with the preconditions of certain rules
and values present and embodied in his the social practices. Since this agent
is active and changing, but socially valued and forming from with that system
of values, the best ethic would be one that creates an environment that allows
diverse action to arise out of the social. Care provides such an ethic because
it focuses on the specifics of situation and the specific needs of each
individual. It at once allows for diversity and fosters the community out of
which it grows. Because the social, emotional context provides the
preconditions for a self in history, fostering those relationships of care provides a greater ability for diverse
action. It focuses on the specific instead of the general, where the general
forces the agent in preformed and unrealistic conceptual boxes. The ethic of Care
allows for the agent to act spontaneously, see his self historically, and to
promote the conditions for his own historical reflections.
Care ethics and
Nietzsche together reveal the insufficient moral theories of justice ethics and
the flimsy foundations out of which Justice ethics forms. They also, with the
help of Foucault possibly provide the first conceptual blocks for an ethical
ideology that takes advantage of realistic agents within a context of realistic
agents all creating a context of care out of which creative, spontaneous and diverse
actions can arise and be recognized as such by both the agent and those around
him.
References:
Foucault (Assigned Reading). The ethics of the concern of the self as a
practice of freedom. Ethics: Subjectivity
and Truth, 281-301.
Held, V.
(1990). Feminist transformations of moral theory, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 321-344.
Jaggar, A.M. (1995). Caring as a
Feminist Practice of Moral Reason, 179-202.
Montanari, D.J. (2011). Nietzsche and “getting it wrong”. Philosophy and Literature, 35, 190-198.
Murchadha, F.O. (2005). Hegel, Nietzsche, Heidegger: thinking freedom and
philosophy, British Journal of the
History of Philosophy, 13, 361-373. doi: 10.1080/09608780500093319.
Nietzsche,
F. W., Ansell-Pearson, K., & Diethe, C. (2007).On the genealogy of
morality. Cambridge Univ Pr.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)